REASON AND AGENCY – Graduate Conference in Philosophy

Events on Campus

2016 Graduate Conference Program

REASON  AND AGENCY
The 16th Annual University of Toronto Graduate Conference in Philosophy
May 5 & 6, 2016

SCHEDULE
Thursday, May 5, 2016
Jackman Humanities Building, (170 St. George St.), Room 100A

9:30 – 10:00     Coffee and Snacks
10:00 – 11:00   ‘Towards an Ecological Libertarianism’ William Hornett (Sheffield)
Commentary: Aaron Henry & Parisa Moosavi (Toronto)

11:15 – 12:15   ‘Some Puzzles about Reasons’ Zachary Blaesi (Texas, Austin) Commentary: Jonathan Payton (Toronto)

12:15 – 1:45     Lunch Break

1:45 – 2:45       ‘What ‘No’ Really Means’ Eleanor Gordon-Smith (Sydney) Commentary: Lisa McKeown (New School)

3:00 – 5:00       Keynote Address
‘Bradley’s Regress and a Problem in Action Theory’ Helen Steward (Leeds)
Commentary: Manish Oza (Toronto)

5:00 – 7:00       Reception (all conference attendees invited)
Location: Jackman Humanities Building, Room 418

Friday, May 6, 2016
Centre for Ethics, Larkin Building (15 Devonshire Place), Room 200

9:30 – 10:00      Coffee and Snacks

10:00 – 11:00   ‘Deontological Evidentialism and the Principle that Ought Implies Can’ Luis Oliveira (UMass, Amherst)
Commentary: Emma McClure (Toronto)

11:15 – 12:15    ‘Because I Said So’
Juan Piñeros Sanchez (Yale) Commentary: John Bunke (Toronto)

12:15 – 1:45      Lunch Break

1:45 – 2:45       ‘Reason, Reasoning, and Weakness of Will’ Jeremiah Carey (Berkeley)
Commentary: Mason Westfall & Rory  Harder (Toronto)

3:00 – 5:00        Keynote Address
‘Retrospection’ Kieran Setiya (MIT)
Commentary: Benjamin Wald (Toronto)

6:00– 8:00          Conference Dinner (for invited guests)
Location: The Host (14 Prince Arthur Ave.)

Abstracts

‘Toward an Ecological Libertarianism – A Defence of Agency Incompatibilism’,
William Hornett

In this paper I will defend Helen Steward’s agency incompatibilism by utilising ecological notions in J.J. Gibson’s work on perception and  action. Steward uses  sub-intentional  actions  as counterexamples to a Davidsonian picture of action and presents a competing  picture which identifies actions as bodily movements controlled by the agent – this forms the basis for her libertarianism  as agential control requires a genuinely open future. Her response  to Mele’s luck objection to libertarianism  is that an act of control is predicated on facts about  agent’s gearing toward the action being integrated into the agent’s history prior to the action. She allows prior facts to constrain  actions  and retains  her libertarianism  by arguing that  the agent’s  freedom  lies in their capacity  to refrain from an action-type  or contour  their execution of an action differently than  they in fact did. However, when she later  on denies  that  all actions  are  done  for reasons,  she  thereby  denies  that  these  non-rational actions  have  explanations at  all. This undermines her  response   to  the  luck  objection  with  regards  sub- intentional actions, because their lacking prior reasons is now a reason to say they are not free. This undermines her  original  argument. I  propose  that  she  need  not  make  that  concession  and  can  instead  use  Gibson’s ecological  approach to  define  sub-intentional  actions  as  affordance-responsive  behaviour  which  shares  a structural  similarity to the way rational actions are reasons-responsive. I then suggest the outline, based on the paper’s previous discussions,  of what I call an ecological conception of freedom: to exercise free will is for an animal  to  intentionally  execute  controlled  responses to  environmental changes  perceived  in virtue  of the animal’s tacit understanding of its own bodily structure, capacities, and cognitive architecture.

‘Some Puzzles About Reasons’,
Zachary Blaesi

Many philosophers working in metaethics take for granted  that the predicates “is a reason for” and “counts in favor of” express or require a common relation, the favoring-relation, which holds of considerations and actions. However, this view encounters a puzzle. For example, suppose  Jones  owes Smith some money and thus has a reason  to pay Smith. In paying Smith, Jones  does what he has reason  to do, and what he does is an action, a concrete particular. But as H. A. Prichard first noted, this concrete  particular does not exist until Jones acts. So, it must  be a mistake  to think that  actions are  relata  in the  favoring-relations  that  hold  before  agents  act. Furthermore, as Roderick Chisholm pointed out, though Jones does what he has reason to do by paying Smith, he could have performed any other number of specific actions while still doing exactly what he has reason to do. This also demands an explanation.  I call the Prichard-Chisholm puzzle the combined  task of explaining what is favored in a favoring-relation and how it relates to particular actions. In my paper, I develop this puzzle in detail and propose a solution.

‘What ‘No’ really means’,
Eleanor Gordon-Smith

One way we can  exercise  our  agency  is by using  words  to  set  the  boundaries of what  other  people  may permissibly do to us. We can say “no”. What sort of speech  act is a refusal? Rae Langton’s anti-pornography argument claims it is an Austinian ‘illocution’, and therefore  that  it depends on ‘uptake’ – recognition  from its addressee – for its success.  Pornography,  goes the argument,  may teach  that  women who say “no” in sexual settings intend to gesture at modesty or to titillate instead of to refuse. This would cause widespread failures of uptake and render some women unable to use the word “no” to perform a refusal; it would rob them of one way to use words to exercise their agency. In this paper I argue that refusal does not require uptake  to succeed.  At least one important function of a refusal is that it marks a boundary around the refuser and declares all conduct over that line to be boundary-crossing. This function is not directed at any agent. It is simply the conjuring of a fact, and so does not depend  on uptake  by the addressee for its success. This means  it can survive an uptake failure like the one Langton describes.  I show that  this function is separate from – and in fact, prior to – the secondary  function of a refusal, which is to deliver a specific prohibition  to a specific person.  It is a speaker’s agency  – not  any epistemic  facts  about  her  interlocutors  – that  lets  her  use  words  like “no” to  wield the normative power of setting her own boundaries. As a final argument in favour of this account  of refusal, I show that it mirrors our pre-theoretic intuition that consent does not depend on uptake either.

‘Deontological Evidentialism and the Principle that Ought Implies Can’,
Luis Oliveira

Deontological  evidentialism  is the claim that  S ought  to form or maintain  S’s beliefs in accordance with S’s evidence. One promising argument for this view turns on the premise that consideration c is a normative reason for S to form or maintain  a belief that  p only if c is evidence that p is true. In this paper, I discuss the relation between  a recent  argument  for this key premise—offered separately  by Nishi Shah (2006) and Ward E. Jones (2009)—and the principle that ought implies can. I argue that anyone who antecendently accepts  or rejects this principle already has a reason  to resist either this argument’s premises  or its role in support  of deontological evidentialism.

‘Because I Said So’,
Juan Piñeros Sanchez

Stephen Darwall has argued that second-personal normativity drives a wedge between practical and theoretical rationality: whereas  it plays a fundamental role in some  areas  of the practical  domain,  it can play at most  a subordinate role in the theoretical one. Darwall’s main argument for this view relies on a picture of theoretical reasoning  as defined by relations between beliefs about  determinate matters  of fact. Partly by questioning  this picture,  I hope  to show that  second-personal normativity  plays as fundamental a role in some  areas  of the theoretical domain  as  well. My  central argument   against  Darwall is based  on  an  analysis  of what  I  call relationships of ‘expectational  trust’, where a person  asks us to believe they will do something  that  is in their power. Such relations, I argue, can give rise to reasons that are theoretical and fundamentally second-personal. The result is a picture of theoretical rationality that  allows for the kinds of rich second-personal relations  that authors like Darwall and Michael Thompson have argued are present  in the practical domain.

‘Reason, Reasoning, and Weakness of Will’,
Jeremiah Carey

In Plato’s  Protagoras, Socrates  defends  an  intellectualist  moral  psychology  –he argues  that  all action  is motivated  by evaluative belief. Plato himself seems to reject this view in the Republic, claiming that  there are three  distinct  sources  of motivation, reason, spirit, and  appetite. Though I  don’t  go into the  details  of this historic dialectic, I want to defend Plato’s side of the general debate. I begin by arguing that weak-willed action could not possibly be an expression of practical reason. Thus, if weak-willed action is possible, we must have a way of acting  intentionally  i.e., for reasons)  in addition  to  our  faculty  of reason.  After showing  how  this argument holds up against approaches from Michael Bratman and Pamela Hieronymi, I say briefly how I think we should respond  to this argument – by accepting  a new tripartite  theory of motivation  consisting of reason, desire, and will.

Thu, May 5, 2016
09:30 PM - 05:00 PM
Room 100A, Jackman Humanities Building
170 St. George St.